Berkeley's Argument
and the Perspectivist Fallacy
David Banach
St. Anselm College
If you can conceive it possible for one extended
movable substance, or, in general, for any one idea, or anything like an idea,
to exist otherwise than in a mind perceiving it, I shall readily give up the
cause
. .
. . . . .
. . . . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . . . .
. . .
But, say you, surely there is nothing easier than for one to imagine trees, for
instance, in a park, or books existing in a closet, and nobody by to perceive
them. ... but what is all this, I beseech you, more than framing in your mind
certain ideas which you call books and trees, and at the same time omitting to
frame the idea of any one that may perceive them. ... but it does not show that
you can conceive it possible the objects of your thought may exist without the
mind. To make out this, it is necessary that you conceive them existing
unconceived or unthought of, which is a manifest repugnancy. When we do the
utmost to conceive the existence of external bodies we are all the while only
contemplating our own ideas. (George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the
Principles of Human Knowledge, I, 22-23.)
I. Introduction: This argument, upon which Berkeley is willing to put so
much weight, is often thought to be obviously invalid because it conflates the
properties of a concept with those of the thing the concept represents. I will
argue that Berkeley's argument does not make this mistake and that the
argument, while still fallacious, is
more subtle and powerful than is commonly thought. In fact, I will argue that it is a form of argument that is common,
and often foundational, in contemporary
thinkers such as Rorty and Putnam, a form of argument I will call the
Perspectivist Fallacy.
II. The Perspectivist Fallacy:
A. Weak version: The argument that representations from
particular perspectives cannot be true or objective, simply because they are
perspectival.
B. Strong version: The argument that representations from
particular perspectives cannot even refer to or be about external objects. (Berkeley's version)
C. Common examples:
1. The
Eternal Why: Every representation of reality is just a representation and
needs further justification. But every justification is just another
representation, which itself needs justification. (Figure 1.)
a. The five year old version.
b. Richard Rorty's version.
2. The
Meaning of Life: Every particular action or value can be questioned from
some more objective point of view. Every justification of any value is always
from some other point of view which itself needs justification. What we do now
won't matter 100 years from now, and, even if it did, what matters 100 years
from now won't matter from some other point of view. Every value requires
external justification. (See Thomas Nagel, The
View From Nowhere, Oxford U. Press, 1986.)
3. "That's
Just Your Opinion": There is no right answer, because every possible
answer is just somebody's point of view. That's just your opinion. (The
implication being that simply because it is an opinion from a particular
perspective, it can't be objective or correct.
III. The Perspectivist Fallacy and the Physical
Model of Representation.
A.
The argument is a non sequitur: Most versions of the argument simply do
not follow unless one takes for granted a particular view of what
representations are and how they represent.
B.
The Physical Model of Representation: This model views mental and
perspectival representation as self-sufficient objects, using the way that
physical objects, such as
pictures, can serve as representations
as a paradigm.
1.
A physical icon, such as a statue, is seen as representing an object in
virtue of its similarity to it. The role that an interpreter plays, in
recognizing the similarity between the icon and the object and projecting the
known properties of the object onto the icon, are overlooked.
(Figure 2)
2.
This incompletely analyzed example is used as the model for mental
representation. In mental
representation, however, there is no question of an interpreter seeing both the
object and the representation, noting their similarities, and projecting the
properties of one onto the other. It is held that we have accesss only to the
mental representation. (Figure 3)
IV.
Berkeley's Argument.
A.
The standard interpretation:
1. Assume material objects exist, and try to
conceive one existing without being conceived in some thinkers mind.
2. In attempting to conceive a material object existing unconceived, you are
attempting to conceive something that is unconceived. This is a manifest
absurdity.
----------------------
By RAA, material objects don't exist.
B.
The standard criticism: This
makes the obvious confusion between the properties of a concept and the
properties of what it refers to. In conceiving a mountain, I don't have rocks
in my head. Hence, in conceiving something unconceived, my concept is not
unconceived, what it refers to is. The contradiction disappears.
C.
A new interpretation:
1. Things represent (refer) in virtue of a
similarity to their object.
2. Nothing can be like an idea, but an idea.
3. A material object, by definition, is unlike an idea.
4. Hence, a concept of a material object is a representation similar to
something it is not similar to. This is a manifest absurdity.
-------------------------
We do not and cannot refer to external objects.
Hence, the things we talk about and refer to (trees, rocks, etc.) cannot be
external material objects.
D.
Putnam's version: This is similar to Berkeley's argument, but the
obstacle to reference is no longer similarity, but the lack of independent
access to extra-mental objects.
V. The Incoherence of the Perspectivist
models of representation and objectivity:
A. Representation: The strong version of the Perspectivist
Fallacy shows that if representations are taken as mental or linguistic objects
that have no intrinsic relation to the object they are supposed to represent or
refer to, and if perspectives are seen to be views of representations not
interactions with or relations to external objects, then representation or
reference will be impossible. That is, representations will not function as
representations. The Perspectivist Fallacy
assumes a model of
representation that views the act of representing as a reified object and,
hence, makes reference and representation impossible. It then goes on to argue that reference to extra-mental objects
is impossible. The conclusion is not surprising, since the view of
representation upon which the argument is based is self-defeating.
B. Objectivity:
Objectivity requires that the representation reflect the object and not the
perspective from which the representation arises. But since a perspective is seen
as a view of the representation only and not a relation to the object, every
perspectival representation can reflect or represent only another
representation or perspective, not reality itself. The attempt to justify our
representations only results in more representations. (The Amazing
Perspectivist Platform.)
VI.
Conclusion: The Perspectivist fallacy ignores the possibility that
representation is an act, not a property of a physical object in isolation from
a representer. If representing is an
act in which we directly interact with the world, particular perspectives must
not only become bearers of knowledge, but the foundations of all knowledge.
Perspectives are not windowless rooms from which there is no escape. They are
themselves windows on the world. They give a limited and incomplete view of the
world, but a view none the less.